CGP DERIVED SEMINAR
GABRIEL C. DRUMMOND-COLE
1. July 18: Byunghee An: Localization of dg categories
I’ll talk about localization of dg categories. So what’s the localization? Let T
be a dg category. We consider [T ] the homotopy category of T and let S be a
subset of the morphisms in [T ]. So then our goal is to define a localization of T
along S, another dg category L
S
T . This should satisfy some condition, regarding
morphisms contained in S as isomorphisms in some sense. This localization in some
sense is a dg localization. What does that mean? Consider a functor, sorry, okay,
from section two, we consider some functor F
T,S
from Ho(dg Cat) Ho(Cat). If
we have a dg category T
then the target category is something F
T,S
(T
) [T, T
].
Basically it is a collection of dg functors up to homotopy, and f is in F
T,S
(T
) if
and only if the induced functor [f] [T ] [T
] sends S to isomorphisms in T
.
So then L
S
T is a dg category such that for any T
, [L
S
T, T
] is a subcategory
of [T, T
] and [L
S
T, T
] is F
T,S
(T
).
Define a functor ` T L
S
T . We call ` a localization of T along S if it
satisfies some universal condition. For any f T T
such that [f](S) lives in the
isomorphisms of T
, then f factors through `, unique up to natural isomorphism.
Proposition 1.1. For any dg category T and for any S in the morphisms of [T ]
there exists a localization ` T L
S
T .
So ` is actually a morphism in Ho(dg Cat).
Before showing the proof, I want to give an easy example. Recall the category
1 with one object and k as self-morphisms. Then
1
k
has two objects 0 and 1 and
a distinguished morphism u from 0 to 1.
What if T is
1
k
? A very simple example. T is [T ] and S = {u}. I’ll construct
`
1
k
1. This sends both objects to and this functor is obvious. I claim that
` is a localization of T along S. In other words it satsifies the universal condition
T
`
||
f
L
S
T
""
T
The universal condition is equivalent to the fact that the `
[L
S
T, T
] [T, T
] is
injective and the image of `
is functors f which take S to isomorphisms.
The induced functor `
[1, T
] [
1
k
, T
] is by precomposition. These were
computed in a previous exercise. We have [1, T
] Iso(T
), the isomorphism classes
of objects of T
. On the other hand, [
1
k
, T
] is the same as isomorphism classes
1
2 GABRIEL C. DRUMMOND-COLE
of morphisms in [T
]. If you have a morphism in [T
], the isomorphism class
means that you can pre- and post-compose with isomorphisms. This functor sends
the isomorphism class of an object to the class of the identity on that object,
[x] [Id
x
]. This is obviously injective.
For the second condition, let’s see what the isomorphism condition is for this
situation. Let f be a morphism in [
1
k
, T
] so [f ] is the same as a morphism
1
k
[T
] and the condition is that [f](u) is an isomorphism. The image consists
of functors in which u is taken to an identity morphism, and thus an isomorphism.
Then the image of `
is a functor which takes u to an isomorphism.
This is a simple example. Let me prove the existence of the localization in the
general case. I want to define L
S
T as a homotopy pushout
S
1
k
//
S
1
T
So let S actually be the set of representing morphisms. We have a canonical mor-
phism
1
k
1, the canonical one, and we also have the map
1
k
T taking u to
the morphism s.
I’ll give a definition of a homotopy colimit. Let D be a diagram like this, a
category, then we can consider C a model category and we can consider the diagram
category C
D
, and we can take the colimit C
D
C. We can construct a functor the
other way by a constant functor. Then actually these two are adjoint to each other
and are a Quillen adjunctions so induce functors on the homotopy category. Then
the left derived functor of the colimit is the homotopy colimit. If D is just the
pushout diagram, then this is just the homotopy pushout.
Now we have an explicit definition of the localization. So how to see that this
is a localization? We have the map from T to L
S
T from it being a (homotopy)
pushout. How about the universal property? Let’s consider T
? Then f sends all
morphisms f to isomorphisms.
Before we have a break, I want to give an exercise. Show that L
u
1
k
is equivalent
to 1. So this is saying that 1
L
1
k
1
k
but this is a cofibrant diagram (trust me on
this), and this is just the regular pushout, but pushing out along the identity gives
the other object.
Okay, the next thing I want to talk is an exercise. Let T and T
be two dg
categories and S and S
collections of morphisms in the homotopy categories of T
and T
as usual, containing all identities. Then the derived tensor L
S
T
L
L
S
T
is
equivalent to L
S
L
S
T
L
T
in the homotopy category of dg categories. We know
T
L
T
but we need to define S
L
S
.
What is the derived tensor product T
L
T
? I erased the definition. This is, in
our paper, this is Q(T ) Q(T
), where Q is a cofibrant replacement functor. So
what’s the right definition of S
L
S
? This is a set of morphisms in the homotopy
categories of morphisms. We can safely use the representing morphisms. We can
in some sense remove the brackets. Then these, I want to say something like
Q(S) Q(S
), this is not defined but let me write this, consider s x y in S. If
we take Q, then we get Qx x and Qy y. We want S
L
S
Mor([T
L
T
]).
How to prove the exercise? I think I’m wrong, but let’s look at the right hand
side. Let M be a C(k)-model category. Look at [L
S
L
S
(T
L
T
),
(M)], this sits
DERIVED SEMINAR 3
in [T
L
T
,
(M)], this should be injective and the image has some property. We
have injectivity here, and by using something we know, by using the universal prop-
erty of the internal homomorphisms, we can move this to [T, RHom(T
,
(M))]
which is the same as [T,
(M
T
)] which is the same as Iso(Ho((M
T
)
T
)), and then
we can switch it around, this is the same as Iso(Ho(M
T T
)), and what I’ve done
is gotten rid of L.
[some discussion of alternate methods]
So instead let’s take `
L
`
T
L
T
L
S
T
L
L
S
T
. So suppose we have a
functor F to T
′′
and suppose it takes morphisms in S
L
S
to isomorphisms, then
we want to lift to L
S
T
L
L
S
T
.
[some more discussion]
The next one is the following proposition.
Proposition 1.2. Let M be a cofibrantly generated C(k)-model category and M is
M viewed as a dg category. Then there is an isomorphism in Ho(dg Cat) Int(M)
L
W
M.
If we invert every weak equivalence in a dg sense, then we get Int(M).
The proof is actually not hard, relatively easier than this exercise. We have a
functor Int(M) M
f
M, the Int(M) is cofibrant and fibrant objects, and M
f
is the fibrant objects. We denote the inclusions
M
f
k
Int(M)
j
;;
i
//
M
and we can define fibrant replacement r and cofibrant replacement q. The existence
of these functors q and r comes from cofibrant generation of M (but you could just
assume them). Then (q j)(x) = q(x) x and (j q)(x) is again q(x), what I
mean is there are natural transformations (q j) id and (j q) id and then
id r k and id k r. These are natural weak equivalences.
Then there are isomorphisms L
W
Int(M) L
W
M
f
L
W
M in Ho(dg Cat). So
what we want to prove is that L
W
(M) Int(M), and my claim is that L
W
(Int(M))
Int(M). Localization means that we want to invert some morphisms in M. We
want to declare certain morphisms to be isomorphisms. But W was already, well,
[Int(M)] Ho(M) M[W
1
]. By the definition of localization we have a functor
Int(M)
`
Ð L
W
Int(M). Then if we have f Int M T
satisfying some condition
then we get a lift from L
W
Int(M). But what’s the condition? It’s that when we
have [Int(M)] [T
] it sends W to isomorphisms. But this condition is vacuous.
So there’s a correspondence.
The next one is the last one:
Proposition 1.3. Let T be a dg-category and S some subset of Mor([T ]), then
` T L
S
T induces a functor `
D(L
S
(T )) D(T ) which is fully faithful and so
that F T C(k) is in im`
if and only if F (S) lands in quasi-isomorphisms.
Proof. D(T )
= Ho(T mod ) and D(L
S
T )
= Ho(L
S
T mod ), and this is the
same as [Int(C(k)
L
S
T
)] which in turn is the same as [RHom(L
S
T, Int(C(k)))].
We are comparing this to [RHom(T, Int(C(k)))]. Then the functor is well-defined
by functoriality of RHom. To prove fully faithfulness, we first consider the functor
4 GABRIEL C. DRUMMOND-COLE
without brackets, `
from RHom(L
S
T, Int(C(k)))
(C(k)
L
S
T
) L
S
T mod to
RHom(T,
(C(k)))
(C(k)
T
) T mod . We have `
from L
S
T mod T
mod , and fully faithfulness there (or the quasi-version) should imply it at the lower
level. But that I didn’t show.
The second condition is easy. The image of `
are the ones that factor through
L
S
T , and so something in S, they must go to quasi-isomorphisms in order to
be isomorphisms in the homotopy category. I couldn’t show the proof for full
faithfulness. But I think this is not too hard.
I want to introduce one last exercise without an answer. The final exercise is
like this.
Let ` be the T L
S
T a localization of dg categories. Then we can consider,
this induces, f T T
induces M
T
M
T
, this is natural because the objects are
functors and we can compose with f . But actually there is a left adjoint f
!
, here
M is a C(k)-model category. This pair is a Quillen adjunction and moreover if f
is an equivalence (isomorphism in the homotopy category) then these are a Quillen
equivalence. This part is Lemma 1, but it uses this fact about f
!
. Especially if f is a
localization, then the left adjoint `
!
exists and its derived functor L`
!
, well, first `
!
T mod L
S
T mod , then the derived functor is on the homotopy categories.
So this is D(T
op
) D(L
S
T
op
). We’ve got a functor between derived categories.
Let W
S
be the morphisms in D(T
op
) such that L`
!
(u) is an isomorphism. The
first question is about classifying the elements of W
S
. I don’t want to talk about
it. The second is more interesting. We can invert W
S
(which satisfies a 2 out of 3
property in D (T
op
)) and the second statement is that D(T
op
)[W
1
S
]
L`
!
Ð D(L
S
T
op
)
and that’s an equivalence of categories. So you can localize either before or after
passing to modules.
I wanted to solve this but I don’t have enough time. I’ll stop.